掠夺型国家
- 格式:pdf
- 大小:108.11 KB
- 文档页数:14
国家自主性:民主政治建构的核心要素摘要:国家自主性是对当前国家自主性过度与国家自主性不足双重困境提出的理论与现实诉求,而民主政治建构则是孕育于国家自主性的制度文化中,国家自主性的不足与过度同样是民主政治建构的泥淖。
基于国家自主性与民主政治建构的内在互构考察,提出国家自主性与民主政治建构的三维写照,即“掠夺型国家”与民主政治建构的先天不足、“俘获型国家”与民主政治建构的可能风险、“参与型国家”与民主政治建构的互动共赢,并在此基础上提出国家自主性与民主政治建构的互促模式:中共领导;政府主导;公民参与。
关键词:国家自主性;民主政治;核心要素“国家自主性(state autonomy)是指国家作为掌握一定领土和民众的机构可以制定和追求并不简单反映社会组织、阶级或整个社会的需求和意愿的目标。
”[1]10“民主政治建构是在中国民主话语体系主导的语汇维度、民主系统政治文化支撑的文化维度、民主政治基本制度完善的制度维度、市场经济发展助推的经济维度的共同助推下逐渐建构的。
”[2]国家自主性是对当前国家自主性过度与国家自主性不足双重困境提出的理论与现实诉求,而民主政治建构则是孕育于国家自主性的制度文化中,国家自主性的不足与过度同样是民主政治建构的泥淖,基于此提出国家自主性是民主政治建构的核心要素。
管窥国家自主性与民主政治建构的内在互构即国家自主性与民主政治形式的共生、国家自主性与民主政治内容的共在、国家自主性与民主政治文化的共存,对国家自主性与民主政治建构的三维写照深入剖析,并由此推演国家自主性与民主政治建构的互促模式。
一、国家自主性与民主政治建构的内在互构国家自主性与民主政治建构从内在机理上透析具有互构性,国家自主性是民主政治建构的核心要素,民主政治建构同样是国家自主性的核心诉求,管窥国家自主性与民主政治建构的内在互构,推知国家自主性与民主政治形式的共生、国家自主性与民主政治内容的共在、国家自主性与民主政治文化的共存。
政治学通识读书笔记一、什么是政治?1.政治是国家兴衰的关键诺思悖论:国家既是经济增长的关键,也是人为的经济衰退的根源儒家:伦理政治观法家(韩非):“经济人”假设和个人主义的方法论。
马基雅维利的政治现实主义古希腊人:城邦是公民参与的统治和管理活动。
雅典:公民大会,五百人议事会。
新英格兰:乡镇精神(托克维尔)西方的现实主义政治观:马基雅维利,韦伯,施密特(政治的核心是“划分敌友”)当代观点:政治可以被理解为发生在一个国家或政治共同体内部的公共领域、涉及采取何种集体决策形式来对公共政策做出选择、并以官僚机构和军队警察作为强制力支撑的一系列活动二、政治学:智者如何思考?什么是可欲的政治秩序,什么是可得的政治秩序。
一种政治秩序的构建较少取决于智者的思考,较多取决于政治参与者的行动哲学传统(注重规范研究)、经验传统(以经验事实为基础)、科学传统(科学方法)学科体系主要包括四个领域:政治哲学、比较政治学(当今最重要)、本国政治、国际政治古希腊与古罗马的传统:希罗多德《历史》对政体问题的讨论。
修昔底德《伯罗奔尼撒战争史》。
柏拉图理论的基础:1.对人性的基本判断,2.任何事情都需要专门的技艺(“现代极权主义思想的滥觞”—波普尔)。
亚里士多德首创了比较研究方法;区分政体类型:1.统治者数量的多寡,2.统治的目的是否服务于全城邦的利益。
西塞罗:混合政体阿奎纳:把亚里士多德的作品系统介绍给西方。
马基雅维利:分离政治与道德。
马丁·路德:因信称义;《九十五条论纲》。
让·博丹:主权学说,充满内在冲突。
霍布斯:《利维坦》从学理上阐明国家的必要性。
洛克:早期自由主义代表,认为统治应基于被治理者的同意,立法权和行政权分立。
孟德斯鸠:反对专制、捍卫自由,三权分立。
卢梭:完善社会契约论,提出主权在民学说,被视为系统阐明民主理论的重要源头。
《联邦党人文集》(分权思想的经典作品):自治政府、代议制、三权分立、自由学说、共和制和联邦制思想;一方面强调分权制衡,一方面强调政府效能经验研究范式:19世纪政治学的主要特征是整体上向经验研究的转向(发掘政治现象背后的因果机制)。
国家掠夺的名词解释随着社会的发展和进步,我们时常会听到一些关于国家掠夺的说法。
那么,什么是国家掠夺?为了能更深入了解这个问题,我们需要先对国家掠夺的概念进行解释。
国家掠夺,简单来说,指的是国家通过不公正的手段,以侵犯个人和社会财富为目的,从个人或社会中获取不义之财。
它是一种直接或间接的权力滥用,往往导致不公平现象的出现。
国家掠夺可以表现在多个层面。
从个人层面来看,国家通过贪污、腐败等手段,将个人财富转移到个别官员或政府机构手中。
这种行为完全违反了法律规定和道德伦理,导致社会财富不公平分配,损害了公平竞争的环境。
在经济层面上,国家掠夺可以体现为过度征税和不合理的税收政策。
当政府过分依赖税收,征收过高的税负时,就会对企业和个人的经济活动产生负面影响。
高税率和繁琐的税收程序会削弱投资者的积极性,限制创新和创造力的发展,进而影响经济的可持续增长。
此外,国家掠夺还可以体现在资源开采和环境保护方面。
一些国家为了获取资源财富,往往对环境进行过度掠夺,不顾环境保护的需求。
这使得自然资源逐渐枯竭,环境恶化,给子孙后代留下了难以弥补的后果。
要解决国家掠夺问题,有几个方面需要特别关注。
首先,建立健全的法制和监管机制至关重要。
只有通过完善的法律体系和监管机制,才能有效打击国家掠夺行为。
这意味着政府应该加强执法力度,确保公正和透明的司法系统,推动廉政建设,减少腐败现象的发生。
其次,要加强公民意识和社会监督。
公民意识的提高可以培养人们对于国家掠夺的敏感度,增加对不公正现象的抵制能力。
同时,社会监督也是防止国家掠夺的重要手段,通过舆论监督,揭露和曝光掠夺行为,可以迫使政府和相关部门改正错误,重视人民的权益。
最后,建立公平、透明和高效的政府机制是解决国家掠夺问题的关键。
政府应该加强自身的建设,优化决策和执行流程,提高透明度和公开度,确保资源的合理分配和公正使用。
当然,解决国家掠夺问题并非一蹴而就,需要政府、公民和社会各方的共同努力。
早期殖民掠夺一、教学要求及教学对象:1.列举进行早期殖民掠夺的国家及其掠夺殖民地的史实,简述“三角贸易”的过程,了解殖民掠夺的影响。
引导学生辩证地理解殖民掠夺的影响,培养论从史出、史论结合的历史思维。
2.绘制简单的“三角贸易”示意图,提高动手能力,理解资本原始积累的野蛮性和残酷性。
3.通过对殖民主义罪恶的认识和批判,培养学生正义感和社会责任感,培养学生关心国家、民族前途命运的精神。
二、基本问题:1.早期殖民掠夺的主要殖民国家: 最早进行殖民的国家是葡萄牙和西班牙、英国、荷兰、法国。
2.早期殖民掠夺的途径方法:占领殖民地、不平等贸易、殖民掠夺、大种植园;“三角贸易”;荷、法、英殖民争霸。
3.早期殖民掠夺的影响:积极影响:加速物种、商品和文化交流;促进世界市场逐渐形成;殖民国家资本原始积累。
消极影响:殖民地国家落后贫穷。
三、播放电视纪录片《大国崛起》的视频片段,情景导入,生成问题师:五百年来,在人类现代化进程的大舞台上,相继出现了九个世界性大国,而其中葡萄牙、西班牙、荷兰和英国则是最早崛起的四个国家。
它们崛起的原因是什么?探究历史,我们会发现,这些大国早期崛起的历史,也正是它们进行残暴殖民掠夺的历史。
今天请同学们跟我一起来学习早期西方殖民史。
利用学生熟悉的影视资源进行课堂导入,激发学生的学习兴趣,并与课堂小结时的探究思考题前后呼应。
四、知识点一葡萄牙与西班牙的殖民掠夺师:通过以下两则材料,西班牙、葡萄牙在早期的殖民掠夺中充分暴露了殖民者贪婪和残暴的强盗本质。
它们为了掠夺殖民地的财富,无所不用其极,主要的手段包括:赤裸裸的抢劫,不惜杀人放火;让殖民地人民做矿工,掠夺殖民地的黄金和白银;从事罪恶的奴隶贸易;实行单一农作物制,抑制殖民地经济发展;增加税收,掠夺财富;等等。
总之,它们不择手段掠夺财富。
材料一:西班牙在殖民地实行残酷的种族奴役政策,使用各种野蛮手段,残暴地杀害印第安人。
其中以科泰斯最为凶残……——李其荣主编:《世界通史.近代卷》,华中师范大学出版社2009年版材料二:葡萄牙人从15世纪起就在非洲西海岸的几内亚、刚果、安哥拉等地设立了许多据点。
The Predatory Stateby James Kenneth GalbraithAugust 2008 5th 2008, Free Press Publishers, 240 pages, 25$Review by DW MacKenzie, PhDThe Coast Guard AcademyCREATED ON: September 5th 2008LAST REVISED ON: September 10th, 2008FORTHCOMING IN: The American Journal of Economics and SociologySUBMITTED ON: September 11th 2008The contents of this paper do not reflect the official views of the Coast Guard AcademyThe Predatory State is an ambitious book. Its author aims at replacing the current global economic system “based on military power, financed through the dollar system” with “a system of collective international security, domestic full employment, infrastructure renewal, and technological leadership” (p206). Professor Galbraith wants to replace “a world ruled by fear with a world ruled by hope”. The troubles of the actual world supposedly lie with failed privatization and deregulation policies enacted by the Reagan and Thatcher Administrations. Privatization and deregulation have allegedly failed to the extent where even Republicans have abandoned free market theories and policies. Free market economics supposedly serves as intellectual cover for the new predator state.The predator state is “a system where entire sectors have been built up to feast upon public systems built originally for public purposes” (p146). To make his case Professor Galbraith examines a variety of domestic issues; tax reform, deregulation of industry and finance, public spending. There are also numerous theoretical issues addressed in this book, as well as references to foreign experiences with privatization. Galbraith identifies Milton Friedman as the most important culprit in advancing privatization and deregulation.The specific claims made by Professor Galbraith are not easily substantiated. Galbraith’s first major claim is that markets cannot and do not think ahead. Planning must be done by the state, directed by the democratic process. Galbraith claims (p166) that since “people not yet born send no market signals … futures markets have nothing to do with preparing for, protecting, or representing the needs of the future”. Galbraith is correct in his assertion regarding markets and future generations, but he fails to recognize that people not yet born also send no political signals through voting or lobbying. One can thus also claim that democracies cannot and do not think generations ahead. Galbraith prefers to attack Neoclassical models that assume immortal agents with perfect foresight. While Neoclassicalmodels are clearly unrealistic, Galbraith’s focus on such models serves only as a diversion from relevant debate over public choice issues. Could his predator state be at least partially the result of regulatory capture and special interest bias? The answer this book provides would seem to be no. On page 24 Galbraith asserts that economic freedom “is terribly limited, compared to political freedom and democracy”. This is, however, and empty and unsupported assertion. The faith that Galbraith exhibits in democratic processes is hardly enough to prove his case for the relative superiority of government planning.Professor Galbraith claims that China has benefited from “the relative absence of a developed market for capital assets … capital markets have limited scope, limited liquidity, and do not exercise discipline” (p83). The Chinese system works because it allows firms to operate while incurring losses. Supervision in China comes from banks, but these banks are state owned, policy oriented, and normally bankrupt (p84). Rather than shutting down firms that incur losses, China allows them to continue operating. China is therefore production driven rather than profit driven. By focusing on production rather than profits “China reproduces the theoretical dynamics and public welfare implications of the perfectly competitive market … precisely because it lacks the essential feature of fully developed capital markets” (p85-86). Here we have the basis for the comparison Professor Galbraith wants to make. He feels justified in holding Western Capitalism to the standard of perfectly competitive equilibrium because China has replicated these results through planning. So when Professor Galbraith claims (p160) that “the existence of externalities and asymmetric information proves that the decisions of thousands of businesses and millions of individuals is not the same as the best achievable result” we can take this statement literally. Professor Galbraith would have us believe that we can achieve the results of an ideal market system of zero transaction costs and perfect information through state planning and hobbled capital markets.Professor Galbraith seems to have joined the long list of scholars who have grossly overestimated Chinese economic performance. While China has posted officials statistics indicating remarkable economic growth in the past thirty years, these numbers have been disproven. Chinese GDP had been thought to have exceeded ten trillion dollars, but a 2007 report by the World Bank indicates that Chinese GDP has only exceeded six trillion dollars. According to Professor Galbraith China has managed to achieve economic perfection, while still having only ⅛ the per capita GDP of the supposedly crippled and inefficient American system of laissez faire financial capitalism.Galbraith’s second major claim that wage determination is a social and not a market decision. The relative distribution of income between labor and capital are not determined by technology or productivity, but society. And society can improve living standards through policies that promote greater income equality. There is, in Galbraith’s view no trade-off between equity and efficiency. We can achieve greater equity and efficiency through the use of the familiar concept of ‘countervailing power’- the “ability of labor, through their union, to raise wages by drawing on the position of the firm” (p119). Professor Galbraith does not consider the possibility that unions could themselves carry out a form of predation. Oddly, professor Galbraith (p38) blames cost push inflation for stagflation. Rising oil prices and union wage demands drove up the cost of living. Is it unreasonable to characterize such transfers as predatory? Is inflation not a tax upon the general consuming population? If union wage demands drove increases in inflation taxes on the general consuming public, then unions are as predatory as any corporation that “feasts upon” the public. The arguments that Professor Galbraith advances for cost push inflation depend upon his weak and highly implausible criticism of Monetarist explanation of Stagflation. Monetarism supposedly failed when tested as “a precise numerical relationship” (p38). Did Friedmanreally claim that there existed a precise numerical relationship between the monetary base and income or inflation? Laidler (1981 p25) regard Monetarism as validated because the money demand function is more stable over time than early opponents of Monetarism suggested, and because shifts in money demand are not large enough to undermine long run relationships between money and nominal income. In fact, experience with Keynesian economic policy has validated the proposition that monetary expansion translates into inflation, after short run adjustments in expectations. Since inflation is a monetary phenomena rather than cost-push driven, labor unions do not appear all that predatory. However, Professor Galbraith’s own arguments run counter to his pro-Union convictions.Galbraith’s claim that equity and efficiency can coexist derives from his view of the effects of capital investment on wages. According to Galbraith the case for improving living standards through private investment is self-contradictory. His argument is simple: efficient private investment requires the full internalization of the returns on investment. Yet if capitalist investors gain the full returns of investment, workers gain nothing. Hence efforts to improve the general well being of society through increased private investment actually benefit only a few economic elites. Were workers to gain something from private investment by capitalists, this would prove the existence of externalities, and externalities indicate market failure. Proponents of free markets would therefore seem to face a dilemma: capitalism either benefits only a few capitalists or it fails to deliver economic efficiency.The argument from the preceding paragraph uses improbable assumptions and faulty reasoning to pose a false dilemma. It is first worth noting that the existence of externalities does not imply that markets are inefficient. Private investment could generate positive infra-marginal externalities to workers, and infra marginal externalities do not affect allocation. A second and more important objection to Galbraith’s argument is that even externalities thataffect the margin of production do not imply the relative inefficiency of private markets. It has long been recognized that private and public institutions are imperfect alternatives, so that imperfections in one do not imply the relative efficiency of the other1. As previously noted, Professor Galbraith believes that the results of perfect competition can be realized through government planning, thought this is obviously impossible.Perhaps the most egregious error in Galbraith’s analysis of investment is in the implicit assumption Galbraith makes regarding labor supply. Capitalist acquire all the gains from trade that derive from capital accumulation if labor supply is infinitely elastic. With elastic labor supply any increases in labor demand that derive from capital accumulation leave wages unaffected, and employers acquire 100% of gains from trade. Galbraith's implicit assumption regarding labor supply is reminiscent of Marx’s claims regarding the reserve army of the unemployed. Capital accumulation will fail to increase wages in the imaginary situation where labor is seemingly abundant. In reality, the marginal opportunity cost of labor rises with increased labor demand. Under real world economic conditions capital accumulation increases labor demand and wages according to marginal productivity, and workers also gain producer surplus of the margin2. Professor Galbraith’s proposition that workers gain nothing from capital accumulation is so contrary to historical experience that one must wonder how it is that he can advance such a claim. As Olson (2000 p49) put it “everyone knows the countries with high per capita incomes have incomparably higher capital intensity”. Yet this obvious fact seems to have eluded Professor Galbraith.1 See Demsetz (1969), Coase (1960), and Mises (1949 p)2 We of course assume that labor and capital are gross complements. Also note that under Galbraith’s assumptions accumulation tends to generate greater employment, albeit at fixed real wages. Workers do therefore gain something, even under his imaginary conditions. However, the least implausible scenario for perfect elasticity of labor supply is the aforementioned Marxist scenario, in which case workers gain additional work only at a subsistence wage.Galbraith claims that tax cuts for the wealthy have not stimulated private savings (p34). For this reason Galbraith characterizes the supply side Reagan tax cuts as a failed policy. Professor Galbraith contradicts himself (p50) on the Reagan Tax Cuts when he admits that “Reagan’s tax cuts were undone in the 1982, 1984, 1986 tax reform acts”. How could he say that tax cuts failed during a time period when they were, in his own words, not in effect?There are also obvious reasons why American savings rates have been low in recent decades. Foreign financial capital has flooded into the US in recent decades. The availability of foreign finance has lowered long term interest rates (Warnock and Warnock 2006). With interest rates low, Americans have little financial incentive to increase savings. There is also evidence indicating that American saving has reached diminishing returns. Scholz, Seshardi, and Surachi () find compelling evidence that eighty percent of Americans who are approaching retirement age have saved ‘optimally’. Smith, McNair, and Love () find that eighty eight percent of Americans over the age of fifty one save at least enough to avoid poverty in retirement. While Galbraith claims that we save according to ‘habits’, the fact of the matter is nearly all of us save according to retirement targets. Since Americans have high incomes and typically experience lower living costs during retirement, low savings rates can be explained by rational choice in the face low interest rates.The Reagan tax cuts “failed to increase savings” because they were undone, and there is little reason for most Americans to increase their current rate of saving anyway. Foreign savings finance much of our private investment and public debt, and nearly all Americans can save enough to avoid poverty even with a low rate of savings. Americans enjoy this advantageous financial position because we have high labor productivity and have the good sense to maintain a relatively secure environment for investment. To put it simply: we arewealthy and secure, and these are good things3. However, Professor Galbraith is not content with this happy situation. He believes that America ought not to be such a safe place for investment. Rather we should substitute public planning for private investment. Lee and Gordon (2004) find a significant negative correlation between corporate taxation and economic performance. In fact, their data indicates that a ten percent cut in corporate tax rates would increase economic growth by one or two percent.Further evidence in favor of developed capital markets exists in the form of data on capital markets in developing nations. Levine and King (1993) find a strong association between the level of financial development and real per capita GDP growth in eighty countries from 1960 to 1989. Developed financial markets correlate with improvements in the efficiency with which economies employ physical capital, and between the predetermined component of financial development and several factors: future rates of economic growth, physical capital accumulation, and economic efficiency improvements. Levine and Servos (1998) find strong correlation between stock market liquidity/bank development and future rates of growth. Borsch-Supan and Romer (1998) find that competitive financial markets reinforce product market competition by cutting off funds to unproductive companies, provided there are competitive threats. Henry (2003) finds that deregulating stock exchanges increases investment and per-worker productivity. Liberalized stock exchanges can also facilitate the adoption of new technologies in developing nations. Henry (2006) finds that liberalized stock exchanges caused a short run increase in economic growth. Argarwal (2001) finds that that stock exchange development has increased economic growth in nine African nations. Argarwal (2007) finds that stock exchange development increases private investment 3 The recent problems in the housing market are an obvious example of current financial insecurity and distress for many. However, we should remember that Fannie Mae was a creation of FDR in 1938. Given the nature of Fannie Mae and Freddie Mac, we can hardly blame the current crisis on free markets, but is instead a product of the general rule that government guarantees lead to moral hazard.and economic growth in twenty-one developing nations. It would seem then that capital markets do direct capital investment with some degree of efficiency, as recognized by Mises (1922) and Hayek (1935) when they critiqued state planning.The failure of Galbraith’s arguments against free capital markets is critical because this failure undermines his case for income redistribution and economic planning. Galbraith claims that since capital accumulation benefits only a few capitalists, tax cuts that supposedly stimulate private investment do not benefit the general working population. It might also have crossed Professor Galbraith’s mind that in his imagined world of elastic labor supply heavy tax increases on capital do not harm the general working population. Professor Galbraith views income distribution as a social matter, by which he means a political matter. He concedes that taxes on capital might infringe upon natural rights of ownership, but why should the right of property stand over the rights of labor to retain earnings (Galbraith p33)? If the decision to tax labor or capital does not affect economic efficiency, then it is a political matter, a matter of power relations between labor and capital.This brings us to the critical issue in Professor Galbraith’s system of arguments: “Economic power naturally translates into political power” (p102). The problem with the predatory society is supposedly that powerful private interests feast upon what are meant to be public resources. Professor Galbraith also claims that wealth concentration leads to the concentration of political power. This is perhaps why he thinks that economic freedom is “terribly limited compared to political freedom”. Markets are, however, pernicious “even if they are perfectly competitive because they entail inequality, and the poor do not matter to the market” (p166). Professor Galbraith’s reasoning is internally consistent up to this point. However, we must remember that he blames our current predicament on the ideas of Milton Friedman (and also on FA Hayek). If wealth inevitably leads to power and power is used forwealth, then it would seem that ideas have little effect on the course of the economic aspects of history. Professor Galbraith switches back and forth between the economic determinism of Marx and proposition that ideas matter as it suites him. If Schumpeter, Keynes, and Hayek are right about the influence of ideas, then The Predatory State has some chance of altering the course of future events, but this proposition undermines a key argument of this book. If ideas matter over material interests, then capitalism is not as dangerous as Professor Galbraith believes. If, on the other hand, material interests matter over ideas, Professor Galbraith’s wasted his time in writing this book. His ideas will change nothing. Also, if material interests matter over ideas, then he is wrong about the causes of the rise of the Predatory state. If economic power leads to political power naturally, then the supposed intellectual cover provided by Milton Friedman for predatory interests was convenient for these purposes, but also unnecessary. It might be possible for Professor Galbraith to argue that there is some kind of interplay or tradeoff between interests and ideas, but this book contains no such concepts. It contains only glaring contradictions.Professor Galbraith gets into further trouble with his rejection of the principle of comparative advantage. He argues that there is a strong case for industrial policy because the original argument for trade according to comparative advantage assumed static conditions (i.e. factor immobility). Of course, this argument makes sense if we accept Galbraith’s assumption that markets cannot and do not plan. It is important to realize that this is an unsupported assumption. Furthermore when we examine the overall record of government planning of industry and compare it to the overall achievements of capitalism, it becomes quite clear that markets can and do plan quite well. We should therefore not only trade according to comparative advantage, we should let capital markets plan out how we develop specific comparative advantages in the pursuit of private profit.Galbraith makes a fair point when he notes that both workers and capitalists have the right to retain honestly acquired incomes. However, his argument that accumulation benefits capitalists only fails in a way that indicates that incomes are determined in a social-economic manner, rather than through a purely social-political process. Improved quality and quantity of capital does increase real wages in line with the discounted marginal productivity of labor. The capitalist system is, contrary to Galbraith’s assertions, a system that determines incomes socially, through exchange and price/wage formation that is relatively efficient. Furthermore, the capitalist system has a proven record of increased real wages and living standards of workers and capitalists alike through capital accumulation.Serious problems exist with Professor Galbraith’s assertion that deregulation has failed. Gwartney et al (2006) find that the impact of private investment on GDP is 74% higher in countries with a high degree of economic freedom. Furthermore, the impact of private investment on development is greater than the impact of public investment. Dawson (2007) finds a negative correlation between most regulation and economic performance. Positive correlations between regulation and economic performance mostly concern types of governmental intervention that make property rights more secure. Borsch-Supan and Romer find that state regulation and ownership are important causes of low capital productivity, both directly and indirectly through limitations of competition. For example, the trade protection of the German and US auto industries and Deutsche Telekom enabled these companies to reap high profits, despite low productivity. Professor Galbraith claims that principled proponents of laissez faire were naïve, and “have been abandoned by history”. Yet actual historical data indicates otherwise. The key problem with The Predatory State at this point is not merely the existence of the aforementioned counterevidence, but the lack of evidence from Professor Galbraith in support of his own position.The Predatory State is meant for a general audience, but it should not mislead this audience. Professor Galbraith is correct in one observation. There are private interests which feed upon ostensibly public institutions. However, proponents of free markets have long opposed large activist governments in part because of the tendency of special interests to capture the benefits of public programs, while leaving the associated costs public. Special interests do posses the advantages in lobbying legislators and capturing regulators. The voting public is by in large rationally ignorant of the dealings between special interests and public officials. The predatory state is not a new phenomenon that emerged as an unintended consequence of Milton Friedman’s pursuit of economic freedom. It is a Public Choice problem.Generally speaking, The Predatory State is a call for state planning not unlike other recent books on Globalization. Professor Galbraith denies the great progress of modern capitalism and proclaims the superiority of governmental planning. He calls for limited governmental planning and with it a dramatic reduction of the importance of markets and competition in society. Professor Galbraith ultimately wants to take steps towards a new international order of global democratic governance. There is nothing really new in his states goals. What is different about this book is that its individual supporting arguments are less well reasoned than even those of Joseph Stiglitz and Jeffery Sachs.BibliographyAgarwal, Sumit. 2001 Stock Market Development and Economic Growth: Preliminary Evidence from African Countries Journal of Sustainable Development in AfricaAgarwal, Sumit. 2007 Stock Market Development and Economic Growth: Evidence from Developing Countries Working PaperAtje, Raymond, and Boyan Jovanovic. 1993. Stock Markets and Development. European Economic Review 37: 632–640.Börsch-Supan, Axel and ; Romer, Paul: 1998. Capital's Contribution to Productivity and the Nature of Competition Brookings Papers on Economic Activity pp205-248Caporale, Guglielmo Maria, Peter G. A. Howells, and Alaa M. Soliman. 2005. Stock Markets Developments and Economic Growth, the Causal Linkage. Journal of Economic Development 29 (1): 33–50.Dawson, J: 2007 Regulation and the Macroeconomy. Kyklos, Blackwell Publishing, V60(1), p15–36.Demirguch-Kunt, Asli, and Ross Levine. 1996. Stock Market Development and Financial Intermediaries: Stylized Facts. World Bank Economic Review 10: 291–321El-Erian, Mohamed A., and Manmohan Kumar. 1995. Emerging Equity Markets in Middle Eastern Countries. Working Paper 94/103. IMF Staff Papers 42: 313–343 Greenwood, Jeremy, and Bruce Smith. 1997. Financial Markets in Development, and the Development of Financial Markets. Journal of Economic Dynamics and Control 21 (1): 145–181Gwartney et al: 2006. Institutions and the Impact of Investment on Growth Kyklos V59 N2 255-273Hayek, FA 1935: Collectivist Economic Planning George Routledge and SonsHenry, Peter "Capital Account Liberalization, The Cost of Capital, and Economic Growth," American Economic Review, 93(2), 2003Henry, Peter "Do Stock Market Liberalizations Cause Investment Booms?" Journal of Financial Economics, 58(1-2), 2000Henry, Peter. 2006 Capital Account Liberalization: Theory, Evidence and Speculation CDDRL Working PaperHenry, Peter 2000 Stock Market Liberalization, Economic Reform, and Emerging Market Equity Prices The Journal of Finance V55, N2 pp. 529-564Levine, Ross. 1991. Stock Markets, Growth, and Tax Policy. Journal of Finance 46 (4): 1445–1465Levine, Ross, and Sara Zervos. 1998. Stock Markets, Banks, and Economic Growth. American Economic Review 88: 537–558Mises, LE von: 1922 [1936]. Socialism, and Economic and Sociological Analysis Liberty Classics 1981 reprintMohtadi, Hamid, and Sumit Agarwal. 2004. Stock Market Development and Economic Growth: Evidence from Developing Countries. Working Paper, University of Wisconsin–MilwaukeeNieweburgh, Stijn van, Frans Buelens, and Ludo Cuyvers. 2006. Stock Market Development and Economic Growth in Belgium. Explorations in Economic History 43 (1): 13–38Levine R. and King R: 1993. Finance and Growth, Schumpeter might be right Quarterly Journal of Economics V108 N3 pp 717-737Mises, LE 1949: Human ActionMises, LE 1922: Socialism, an Economic and Sociological Analysis. Liberty Press, 1981 reprint, 1936 translationWarnock, F and Warnock, V 2006 International Capital Flows and US Interest Rates NBER Working Paper #12560. Subsequently published in the Journal of International Money and Finance。