Habitus and Utopia in Science;Bourdieu,Mannheim,and the Role of Specialties in the Scientific Field
- 格式:pdf
- 大小:114.79 KB
- 文档页数:15
Was Einstein a Space Alien原文及翻译Was Einstein a Space Alien原文及翻译原文:Albert Einstein, one of the greatest minds in the history of science, is known for his groundbreaking theories and contributions to the field of physics. However, there have been persistent rumors and speculations that Einstein was more than just a brilliant scientist – some believe that he may have been a space alien. This article delves into the evidence, myths, and theories surrounding the idea that Einstein was a visitor from outer space.Einstein was born on March 14, 1879, in Ulm, Germany. From a young age, he showed a profound interest in mathematics and physics. His exceptional intellect and ability to think outside the box allowed him to develop revolutionary concepts, such as the theory of relativity. However, some people argue that his extraordinary abilities were not entirely human in origin.One theory suggests that Einstein's incredible intelligence and revolutionary ideas were the result of extraterrestrial intervention. According to proponents of this hypothesis, Einstein's ideas were too advanced for a mere mortal and could only have come from a more advanced civilization. They speculate that Einstein was a vessel for extraterrestrial knowledge, sent to Earth to enlighten humanity.Another aspect often pointed out is Einstein's physical appearance. Some claim that his distinctive features, such as his wild hair and intense gaze, resemble the stereotypical image of aliens depicted in popular culture. This has led some to believe that Einstein's appearance was evidence of his extraterrestrial origin.Additionally, skeptics argue that Einstein's breakthroughs in science were too unconventional to have been achieved through purely human means. They suggest that his insights into the nature of space and time were the result of otherworldly guidance. Some even go as far as suggesting that he had access to advanced technology and knowledge that had been shared by extraterrestrial beings.Despite these compelling arguments, it is important to approach these theories with a skeptical mind. The idea that Einstein was an alien lacks solid evidence and is largely based on speculation. While his intellect and contributions to science were undoubtedly extraordinary, they can be explained by his own brilliance and dedication to his work.翻译:艾因斯坦是太空外星人吗?艾因斯坦是科学史上最伟大的思想家之一,以他的开创性理论和对物理学领域的贡献而闻名。
第15卷第2期2002年4月烟台大学学报(哲学社会科学版)Journal of Yantai Univ ersity(Philosophy and Social Science)Vol.15No.2Apr.,2002布迪厄场域理论简析李全生(烟台大学社科德育部,山东烟台264005)[摘要]皮埃尔#布迪厄是国际知名的法国社会学家,他的场域理论是其社会学体系中的重要内容。
场域这一概念和分析单位来自他早年的人类学研究,场域中充满着力量和竞争,个体可选择不同的竞争策略,资本既是竞争的目的,又是竞争的手段。
场域有自主化的趋势,但场域本身的自主性又受到外来因素的限制。
惯习是与场域对应的一个基本概念,惯习与场域紧密结合。
布迪厄通过场域理论,为实践自己的社会学宗旨,为超越主客观二元对立,做出了较为成功的尝试。
[关键词]场域;惯习;资本[中图分类号]C91[文献标识码]A[文章编号]1002-3194(2002)02-0146-05皮埃尔#布迪厄(Pierre Bourdieu)是继M#福柯之后,法国又一具有世界影响的社会学大师,他和英国的A#吉登斯、德国的J#哈贝马斯一起被认为是当前欧洲社会学界的三大代表人物,他的思想和著述在国际学界广受重视,20世纪90年代中期以来,也引起了我国社会学者的注意。
布迪厄称得上学术杂家,他的社会学中融入了人类学、教育学、哲学、艺术、语言学、历史、文化学等诸学科的内容,可谓包容丰富、错综复杂。
一般认为,场域理论是他的基本理论,在其社会学思想体系中占有最重要的地位。
因此,本文试图对布迪厄的这一理论进行简要的分析。
一、场域和资本对于场域(field)这一概念,布迪厄这样说过: /我将一个场域定义为位置间客观关系的一网络或一个形构,这些位置是经过客观限定的。
0[1](P39)布迪厄的场域概念,不能理解为被一定边界物包围的领地,也不等同于一般的领域,而是在其中有内含力量的、有生气的、有潜力的存在。
中考英语经典科学实验与科学理论深度剖析阅读理解20题1<背景文章>Isaac Newton is one of the most famous scientists in history. He is known for his discovery of the law of universal gravitation. Newton was sitting under an apple tree when an apple fell on his head. This event led him to think about why objects fall to the ground. He began to wonder if there was a force that acted on all objects.Newton spent many years studying and thinking about this problem. He realized that the force that causes apples to fall to the ground is the same force that keeps the moon in orbit around the earth. He called this force gravity.The discovery of the law of universal gravitation had a huge impact on science. It helped explain many phenomena that had previously been mysteries. For example, it explained why planets orbit the sun and why objects fall to the ground.1. Newton was sitting under a(n) ___ tree when he had the idea of gravity.A. orangeB. appleC. pearD. banana答案:B。
好奇推动科学进步作文English Response:英文回答:Curiosity has been the driving force behind scientific progress for centuries. From the early days of exploring the cosmos to the intricate world of quantum mechanics, human curiosity has led to groundbreaking discoveries and innovations. Personally, I believe curiosity ignites the spark of exploration within us, propelling us forward in our quest for knowledge and understanding.One of the prime examples of curiosity drivingscientific progress is the discovery of penicillin by Alexander Fleming in 1928. Fleming's accidental observation of mold inhibiting bacterial growth sparked his curiosity, leading to the development of the first antibiotic. This chance discovery revolutionized medicine and saved countless lives, all because of one curious scientist'sobservation.Moreover, curiosity often leads to unexpected breakthroughs. Take the story of Percy Spencer, the inventor of the microwave oven, for instance. While working on radar technology during World War II, Spencer noticed that a candy bar in his pocket had melted due to the microwaves emitted by the radar equipment. His curiosity about this phenomenon ultimately led to the invention of the microwave oven, a kitchen staple in households worldwide.In my own experience, curiosity has been a driving force in my academic pursuits. Whenever I encounter a puzzling question or an unexplained phenomenon, mycuriosity pushes me to delve deeper, to ask more questions, and to seek answers through experimentation and research. This insatiable curiosity has not only expanded my knowledge but has also shaped my approach to problem-solving and critical thinking.Furthermore, curiosity fosters collaboration andinterdisciplinary research. When scientists from different fields come together to explore a common curiosity, remarkable discoveries often emerge. For instance, the discovery of the Higgs boson, a fundamental particle in particle physics, was the result of collaboration between physicists, engineers, and mathematicians, each driven by their curiosity to unravel the mysteries of the universe.In conclusion, curiosity is the driving force behind scientific progress, fueling our desire to explore the unknown and pushing the boundaries of human knowledge. Itis the curiosity of individuals that has led to some of the most significant scientific breakthroughs in history, shaping the world we live in today.中文回答:好奇心几个世纪以来一直是推动科学进步的动力。
文化资本(le capital culturel)是一种已被广为接受的社会学概念,由皮耶·布迪厄首先提出。
布迪厄和让–克洛德·帕斯隆于《文化再制与社会再制》一书中首次使用到了此一名词。
在本书中,他试图去说明法国在1960年代间教育支出的不同。
之后经过了再次地阐述和发展之后,文化资本在《资本的形式(The Forms of Capital)》中被指为另一个形式的资本,并在《国家贵族(The State Nobility)》中被指为较高等的教育。
对于布迪厄来说,资本在一个交易系统中扮演着一种社会关系,而且这一词并延伸至指所有不论是物质性的或是象征性的商品,那些商品是稀有的且在特定的社会组成之下是值得去追寻的。
而文化资本即是指包含了可以赋予权力和地位的累积文化知识的一种社会关系在《资本的形式》中,布迪厄区分出了三种类型的资本:∙经济资本:对经济资源(钱、财物)的拥有。
∙社会资本:群体上的资源、关系、影响与扶持的网络。
布迪厄定义社会资本为“拥有相识和认可等多少有些制度性关系的坚固网络,这些实际或潜在资源的总和”。
∙文化资本:知识的类型、技能、教育、任何一种个人可以让他自己在社会上获得较高地位的优势,包括他人对自己高度的期许。
父母给与孩子们文化资本,可以把教育体系变成舒适且熟悉的地方而使他们易于成功的态度及知识。
∙内含文化资本是指内含于个人的文化资本。
.∙具体文化资本是指如科学制置或艺术作品等物品。
这些文化产品可以物理性地做为经济资本被转移(卖出),且“象征性”地做为文化资本。
然而,一个人虽然可以经由拥有一幅画来得到具体文化资本,但若他有着相应类型的(因画的转买而可能或不会被转移的)内含文化资本,他就可以只是“消费”这幅画(了解其文化意涵)。
∙制度文化资本是指个人所持有的文化资本在制度上被认可,一般最常指的是学业证书或执照。
这主要是在劳动市场里被认知。
它允许文化资本能较为简易地被转变成经济资本,经由对成就在制度上的等级加以给定其金钱价值。
Pierre Bourdieu布迪厄:语言与象征权力Language and Symbolic Power语言是什么?这是一个大难题。
我们学文学、语言、哲学和历史的博士生,读书越多,反而越糊涂:索绪尔说语言是一套严谨自律、抽象静止的“符号系统”。
在哈贝马斯看来,语言是一种不分贫贱、童叟无欺的“普遍交往”。
可在法国社会学家布迪厄目中,语言带有象征力量,其中隐含了福柯所说的“话语权力”。
索绪尔所谓的符号系统,虽然具备某些内在法则,它更是一套象征性的统治工具。
凭借这一隐秘难见的象征权力,西方发达资本主义社会及其文化网络,因而获得了天网恢恢、无处不在的政治功能、以及一种长期延续、自我循环的文化再生产逻辑。
布迪厄的见解从何而来?让我们回到新左派革命时期,去看看当时巴黎高师的学术与政治语境。
1970年,福柯入选法兰西学院,隆重讲演《话语的秩序》(The Order of Discourse)。
此文宗旨,是要以一种新式冲突论,“就西方知识的历史命运,作出政治性解答”。
然而其中关键,并非马克思的阶级斗争,而是尼采喋喋不休的权力意志。
何谓权力意志?根据尼采,它首先是一种力(Macht)。
如何让这种力量获得胜利呢?尼采说:“赋予它一种内在意志,我称为权力意志”。
对于福柯,尼采是个“权力哲学家”:他不但描述权力争斗、张扬强悍意志,而且率先将权力关系,“指定为哲学话语的核心”。
福柯拓展尼采权力观,使之广泛牵扯到:[1] 西方人上天入地、孜孜求知的浮士德精神,[2] 西方人对于“他人”和世界的征服能力;[3] 西方现代机构及其先进精密的统治技术。
尼采权力说,暗藏了他对西洋真理的一大讽喻:古希腊人原本善良天真,他们相信话语的力量,就在于谁说话、怎样说、在何种场合说。
那时节,长老在庄严仪式中发号施令,巫师神秘兮兮念动咒语。
大群愚昧听众,无不诚惶诚恐、心悦诚服。
谁知道,阴微小人柏拉图,竟从长老、国王和巫师的说话仪式中,窥见了垄断真理的手段:原来话语权力,来自神秘言说及其仪式!于是柏拉图发明辩证法、组建专家群,继而著书办学,自诩是苏格拉底的传人,从此他独揽了西方真理。
英文版《实践论》on practice"The Practice of Practice" is a work written by French philosopher and sociologist Pierre Bourdieu. This book was translated into English under the title "On Practice." 《实践论》是法国哲学家和社会学家皮埃尔·布迪厄所著的著作。
这本书被翻译成英文,标题是《On Practice》。
Bourdieu's "On Practice" explores the concept of practice as a form of social action that contributes to the reproduction and transformation of social structures. Bourdieu argues that practice is not only a matter of individual choice, but is shaped by social and cultural forces. Bourdieu的《实践论》探讨了实践的概念,将其视为社会行为的一种形式,有助于社会结构的再生产和转变。
Bourdieu认为,实践不仅仅是个人选择的问题,而是由社会和文化力量塑造的。
One of the key ideas in "On Practice" is the concept of habitus, which refers to the deeply ingrained habits, dispositions, and tastes that are developed through a person's socialization and shape their actions and outlook on the world. Bourdieu argues that habitus serves as a generative principle that guides and structures individual practices.《实践论》中的一个关键观念是habitus的概念,它指的是通过个人社会化而形成的根深蒂固的习惯、性格和品味,塑造了他们的行为和世界观。
布爾迪厄《學術人》(Homo Academicus)導讀黃庭康南華大學社會學研究所布爾迪厄的《學術人》一書是他其中一部主要的教育社會學作品。
該書的法文版於一九八四年出版。
四年後英文版面世,由Polity Press出版。
布氏《學術人》一書以法國高等教育體系為研究對象,內容涉及不同等級學校教授與學生的出身背景、大學與階級再製、大學內部的權力關係、高等教育的再製(reproduction)模式、以及教授們的政治行為等。
《學術人》一書的價值可以分為幾方面。
首先,傳統上教育社會學一般以中、小學為研究的對象。
就是研究大學,焦點也偏重於學生,極少深入剖析教授。
這是教育社會學發展的一大遺憾,因為高等教育的教研人員扮演文化生產及再製(cultural production and reproduction)的重要角色,對他們認識不足有礙我們對教育與權力的了解。
《學術人》一書填補教育社會學的這一個重要的空白,也打破了不少我們對大學的迷思。
1其次,布爾迪厄與不少晚近的教育社會學學者一樣,都注意到教育體系的矛盾性格---它一方面灌輸保守的意識型態、維持不平等的社會現狀;但同時又鼓吹批判、懷疑既有的權力關係(Apple, 1985; Carnoy and Levin, 1985)。
《學術人》一書的其中一大貢獻就是以布爾迪厄之前發展出的資本(capital)、場域(field)、生存心態(habitus)、及策略(strategy)等概念解釋大學這矛盾的性格。
布氏以各類型大學教授所擁有的資本、在場域所占的位置、他們的生存心態、及由此而衍生的策略解釋為何有些教授傾向保守、有些教授思想離經叛道。
此外,《學術人》一書亦豐富了關於教育體系相對自主性(relative autonomy)的討論。
自從鮑爾斯與堅迪斯(Samuel Bowles and Herbert Gintis)於一九七六年出版《資本主義美國的學校教育》(Schooling in Capitalist America)後,批判取向的教育社會學學者一直為了對抗符應理論(correspondence theory)而討論教育體系的相對自主性(Apple, 1979, 1985, 1993; Bernstein, 1986, 1996; Girous, 1983; Willis, 1977)。
关于空间理论的简析随谈福柯(Michal Foucalt)对权力的空间向度进行了深刻的剖析,在他眼中现代社会是铜墙铁壁的监狱是四散飘零的群岛,密不透风是其主要特征,全景敞视监狱就是空间施展权力的集中体现,不仅仅是监狱,在医院、学校、军营、工厂都可见权力发生的的微观运行。
权力技术与知识话语紧密地联系着,空间被赋予话语体系即是权力的运作。
分界与区隔是权力管制的方略,不同的人被放置到某一空间内,也就被归置到相应的地位,从而形塑了人的日常生活方式和行为方式。
比如圆形监狱的塔楼内,被监视者无法确知是否有监视者在内,但会产生自我监视自我控制,永远都无法挣脱。
权力通过空间来改造身体,人的身体时刻处于权力网络之中,被改造成服从的身体。
最终提出了异托邦(Heterotopia)这个概念,不同于乌托邦的本不存在,它是可触碰可进入的,是多元的异质文化的共时性同存的空间,也是时间不断聚集积累的空间。
进入异托邦需要一些许可,隔离与进入基本自由,是逃脱主流同一性叙述进行一种差异规划的空间。
无论如何自我劝诫无论怎样深信被说服的规范,只要产生了质疑,就能突破与改变,蕴含着革命的契机。
布尔迪厄(Pierre Bourdieu)理清了地理空间与社会空间两者的复杂关系,建立起以实践和社会行动为核心的地理学。
在他的理论中,最有解释力的莫过于“资本-惯习-场域”的三元分析,三者关系可表示为——[资本+惯习]+场域=实践。
资本(Capital)在马克思那里被定义为累积起来的抽象劳动,大多是物质化的,而他则拓宽了这个概念的意涵,即凡是可以作为一种社会权力关系来发挥作用的任何资源都是资本。
经济资本(如金钱)社会资本(如人际网络)文化资本(如审美品味、语言叙事、文凭职称)是资本的三种形式,分别以客观形态、身体形态、制度形态呈现。
场域(Field)是各种位置之间的客观关系的一个网络,这些位置根据资本的不同类型和数量进行界定,占有某个位置即占有相应的权力,资本赋予了对场域进行控制和支配权力,它可以配置物质或身体上的生产或再生产工具、可以决定日常运作的常规,以及从中获取的特定的利润。
Studies in Sociology of Science Vol. 2, No. 1, 2011, pp.22-36 ISSN1923-0176[P RINT]ISSN1923-0184[O NLINE] 22Habitus and Utopia in Science: Bourdieu, Mannheim, and the Role of Specialties in the ScientificFieldRichard M. Simon1Abstract:Pierre Bourdieu has claimed that his concept of the habitus resolves theobjectivism/constructivism debate in the sociology of science. While institutional norms require that scientists maintain a disinterested attitude, studies have revealedthat scientists often fail to live up to the normative standard of disinterestedness, sometimes becoming highly tendentious to promote their own work. Bourdieu resolves the interested/disinterested paradox by claiming that scientists promote theirown personal interests through objective science. This is supposed to be the consequence of the scientific habitus, which ensures that the biases of the scientificfield remain invisible to scientists who operate within it. The concept of the habitus iscentral to Bourdieu’s theory of science. However, it has suffered from two majorshortcomings: 1) the scientific field is made up of clusters of specializations which areshaped by interactions with each other, and the habitus does not account for thesemesolevel interactions; 2) it can only account for reproduction of the scientific fieldand therefore ignores the mechanisms which produce change. I argue that Karl Mannheim’s sociology of knowledge may be employed to better understand how theproperties of scientific specialties both reproduce interested and disinterested behavior among scientists and facilitate change in particular specialty areas.Key words: Pierre Bourdieu; Karl Mannheim; Habitus; Utopia; Field Theory;Specialization; Constructivism; Objectivism; Scientific ChangePierre Bourdieu (1975, 2004) has claimed that his concept of the scientific habitus resolves the objectivism/constructivism debate in the sociology of science. While institutional norms require that scientists maintain a disinterested attitude (Merton, 1968), empirical work in the sociology of sciencehas revealed that scientists often fail to live up to the normative standard of disinterestedness, sometimes becoming highly tendentious to promote their own work (Arthur, 2009; Frickel, 2004; Frickel & Gross, 2005; Fuchs & Plass, 1999; Griffith & Mullins, 1972). Bourdieu contends accepting the legitimacy of scientific knowledge at face value, and conceptualizing it as politics by other means, are two unsatisfactory options. Clearly, the production of scientific knowledge is shaped more by political forces than positivistic accounts have acknowledged (e.g., Collins & Pinch, 1998). Yet Bourdieu warns against throwing the baby out with the bathwater; it is equally misleading to overlook the role the disinterested scientific attitude plays in how scientists produce knowledge (Bourdieu, 1990).The commitment to disinterested, objective science, and the demonstrated role that interests play in the 1 Department of Sociology, Pennsylvania State University, 211 Oswald Tower, University Park, PA 16802, United States. Email: rms386@* Received May 10, 2011; accepted May 25, 2011.construction of scientific facts (Latour & Woolgar, 1979; Latour, 1987) result in a paradox of motivation.Bourdieu resolves the interested/disinterested paradox by claiming that because disinterestedness is a regulatory norm, scientists promote their own personal interests through objective science. Bourdieu points out that, in the scientific field, consumers of scientific products are also the producer’s rivals, and this rivalry is played out by constantly pushing one’s self, and one’s opponents, to better conform to scientific rationality (2004). In this way scientists exhibit interested behavior while simultaneously adhering to the norm of disinterestedness. The theoretical advancement that is supposed to explain simultaneous interested and disinterested behavior is the scientific habitus, which ensures that the biases of the scientific field remain invisible to scientists who operate within it. The habitus is a social-psychological framework for scientists to appraise new scientific developments that is based on communally agreed upon standards. Because the habitus is a consequence of existing norms, it reproduces the scientific field by providing a template for behavior that is based on preexisting expectations (Bourdieu, 2004).Scientists pursue their own interests by subjecting their rivals to exacting standards of scientific rationality imposed by the habitus (Bourdieu, 2004). Each new piece of information that is relevant to a scientist’s own career can be interpreted as corroborating or contradicting his or her own research program, and Bourdieu proposes that scientific rationality is a weapon used by scientists to neutralize scientists who make contradicting claims, and assimilate scientists who make corroborating claims. But scientists involved may not necessarily be aware that they are using rationality in a partisan way; because disinterestedness is an integral element of scientific rationality, scientists can use it to pursue their own interests while simultaneously being committed to disinterestedness. Bourdieu thus claims that a kind of positivistic scientific rationality plays a role in the accumulation of scientific knowledge, but also acknowledges that the scientific field is stratified by non-scientific factors (i.e., personal interests). The chasm between scholarship which assumes scientists engage in disinterestedness and that which characterizes science as politics by other meanshas traditionally been wide and that Bourdieu has been able to reconcile these views is a major achievement.The concept of the habitus is central to Bourdieu’s theory of science, but it suffers from some major shortcomings: Firstly, Bourdieu fails to account for an integral element of the structure of the scientific field: specializations. Scientific specialties are clusters of scientists who share common interests and who work toward common goals. Specialties are one of the most salient elements of intellectual and professional identity among scientists (e.g., Griffith &Mullins, 1972; Mullins, 1972, 1973; Lermaine, MacLeod, Mulkay & Wiengart, 1976;Hargens, Mullins & Hecht,1980; Glaser, 2001; Frickel & Gross, 2005), and so an account of the scientific habitus cannot overlook the effect participating in a specialty has on establishing the scientists’ interests. Moreover, the habitus associated with a specialty is in part shaped by that specialty’s interaction with other specialties and other parties outside of the scientific field. Individual scientists do not compete for scientific capital as individuals alone; they do it in the context of the particular specializations in which they participate, and these specializations have a logic which shapes the scientific habitus at a higher level of analysis than practices involved with developing and carrying out individual research projects. Bourdieu’s field theory of science would explain more if it could account for the properties of specialties and the way they interact with other groups.Another shortcoming of the habitus as applied to science is that it can only account for reproduction of the scientific field and therefore ignores the mechanisms that produce change. Bourdieu has often been accused of focusing too much on social reproduction and not enough on social change. This criticism is especially relevant when applied to the scientific field, which has mechanisms designed to facilitate change built into its logic (i.e., organized skepticism; Merton, 1968). If the habitus is to retain explanatory power in the field of science, it must account for changes in the scientific field.I will argue that Karl Mannheim’s sociology of knowledge may be employed to better understand the relationship between scientific specialties and the scientific habitus. I will also argue that Mannheim’s conceptualization of utopianism can help explain how the scientific habitus both reproduces the scientific field and simultaneously facilitates its evolution. Mannheim’s structural perspective and his analysis of the relationship between thought structures and group positions provide theoretical insights into Bourdieu’s field theory of science. The key insights which Mannheim offers to Bourdieu’s field theory are that utopian thought is critical, ideological, and based on group positions. From this23Mannheimian perspective, the scientific habitus is shaped by the collective experiences of scientists within their own specialties, including interactions with other groups, both inside and outside of science. Moreover, the progressive orientation of scientific utopias ensures a scientific field which is not just reproduced, but in constant flux. These insights will be applied to a well-known case study in the sociology of scientific specializations, Scott Frickel’s Chemical Consequences (2004). In this book Frickel shows how genetic toxicologists came to define and redefine their own scientific field, and it serves as an example of how Mannheimian insights can be applied to Bourdieuian field theory.2 BOURDIEU, FIELD THEORY, AND THE SOCIOLOGY OFSCIENCEBourdieu’s field theory is a general theory that has been used to explain myriad social phenomena. The three core concepts in Bourdieu’s field theory are “field”, “habitus”, and “symbolic capital” ( Bourdieu, 1977). The field represents all individuals within a more or less autonomous social world who have interests and compete for resources, in particular symbolic capital. Each field has its own logic (what Bourdieu calls “specificity”) that is determined by the regularities of behaviors of the individuals who participate in the field. Conditions for entry into a field are competence (the ability recognize, react to, and ultimately internalize the regularities of the field) and belief (basic properties of the field will not be questioned; this secures the autonomy of the field) (Bourdieu, 2004). The idea of a “field”, a metaphor taken form physics, is that diffuse “forces” surrounding an object have the capability of changing that object. A field is “the local social world in which actors are embedded and toward which they orient their actions” (Sallaz and Zavisca, 2007: 24). In his review of field theory, Martin explains, “In the social sciences, the field serves as some sort of representation for those overarching social regularities that may also be visualized (by competing theoretical orientations) as quasi-organisms, systems, or structures” (2003: 8). Individuals in a field share a relationship to each other through a shared logic, goals, and recognized forms of legitimate compensation and reward. Fields have “rules for how to play, stakes or forms of value (i.e., capital), and strategies for playing the game. In the process of playing, participants become invested in and absorbed by the game itself” (Martin, 2003:24). While the struggle for resources is a “game” with “rules”, the concept of “rules” in a field refers to the patterned behaviors of the actors within it who choose the behaviors which bring the most rewards, not formal decrees. A field is comprised of“a set of assumptions always vulnerable to deliberate upset via surprise” (Martin, 2003: 32); that is, the rules can be broken. More technically, when the field changes in such a way that the old patterns of behavior are no longer profitable, actors will adjust their behavior accordingly and the patterns will change, bringing about new “rules of the game”.The most important reward at stake in a field is symbolic capital. Symbolic capital is a universally agreed upon reward or item of value relevant to a field. Anything can serve as symbolic capital if people recognize its unequal distribution as legitimate (Bourdieu, 1991: 118). In the labor market symbolic capital may refer dirtiness/cleanliness of a job or the flexibility of the work schedule; in science symbolic capital may refer to publications in elite journals or access to elite methods or equipment. By emphasizing the importance of symbolic capital Bourdieu does not deny the importance of material conditions, but argues that all rewards, including material, will flow to those who have the symbolic authority to possess them.In Bourdieu’s field theory the regularities that constitute a field become internalized by the individuals, and the structure of thought is shaped by these external forces. This internalization of social structure is termed the habitus. The habitus is defined by Bourdieu as a set of “durable, transposable dispositions” (1991: 53). It “is less a set of conscious strategies and preferences than an embodied sense of the world and one’s place within it—a tacit ‘feel for the game’” (Sallaz and Zavisca, 2007: 25). The habitus is theoretically useful because it is a social-psychological concept which accounts for the reproduction of 2 Scott Frickel did not draw upon Pierre Bourdieu or Karl Mannheim in his analysis of chemical mutagenesis in Chemical Consequences. My own thesis is based entirely on my own use of their ideas to interpret Frickel’s empirical findings.24social structure. The habitus is best thought of as a kind of coupling connecting the individual to the logic of the field. It determines the structure of an individual’s consciousness in such a way that resources required from the individual to maintain social structure, and the rewards the social structure delivers to the individual for cooperation, may be exchanged with the least amount of disruption, to the point that an individual’s habitus goes largely unnoticed by the individual until the field’s autonomy is threatened by external powers (Bourdieu, 1977). Consequently, the habitus enables the social structure of the field to be reproduced, at the same time that the field determines the shape of the habitus.Bourdieu applied his brand of field theory to many areas of social life, including the scientific field. In the field of science, symbolic capital derives from access to and skill in the most prestigious objects, methods, theories, and equipment. The “rules of the game” are shaped by the strategies scientists need to have to secure this scientific capital (including securing the right mentors and colleagues, learning the right methods, using a specific kind of technical language, etc.), and the scientific habitus determines which kinds of scientific problems are the most important, and what will be taken for granted. The scientific habitus is supposed to reproduce structures of power within the scientific field by setting priorities which benefit those who already have disproportionate access to scientific capital (Bourdieu, 1975, 1988, 2004).Bourdieu claims that his concept of the habitus resolves the objectivism/constructivism debate in the sociology of science. He points out that, in the scientific field, “producers tend to have as their clients only their most rigorous and vigorous competitors, the most competent and the most critical, those therefore most inclined and most able to give their critique full force” (2004: 54), and this rivalry is played out by constantly pushing one’s self, and one’s opponents, to better conform to scientific rationality. In this way scientists exhibit interested behavior while simultaneously adhering to the norm of disinterestedness. The solution he offers is, essentially, that being “objective” is part of the “rules of the game” in the scientific field, and so scientists actively try to play the disinterested part, though because of their habitus that “objectivity” is biased in a direction which reflects their interests. Therefore, scientists can be objective while simultaneously being biased; their strategies are inseparably social and scientific.“It follows”, Bourdieu argues, “from a rigorous definition of the scientific field as the objective space defined by the play of opposing forces in a struggle for scientific stakes, that it is pointless to distinguish between strictly scientific determinations and strictly social determinations of practices that are essentially overdetermined” (1975: 21).That is, the logic of the scientific fieldengenders a habitus which motivates scientists to adopt norms of scientific objectivity, but at the same time biases standards of objectivity toward the individual interests stemming from participating in a certain place in the field. Scientists are committed to a particular way of doing science, and attempt to produce objective, scientific results within the limits of their habitus.Despite the utility of the concept of the habitus in science, Bourdieu’s discussion of how the habitus is constructed from experiences in the field is limited. The scientific habitus is treated as a universal construct governing the relationship between the logic of the scientific field and individual scientists, but little attention is given to how scientific expectations dictated by specific research specialties produce the habitus. Bourdieu’s major empirical research on scientific capital, published as Home Academicus (1988), compares only broad disciplinary orientations (law, medicine, science, and the arts) within academia, and fails to examine specific research programs and how they shape the positions and dispositions of the scientists who work within them. The scientific habitus is supposed to reflect a relationship between individual scientists (the habitus is essentially a social-psychological concept) and the organization of the scientific field as a whole, but Bourdieu pays little attention to the mesolevel aspects of scientific organization which play a major role in shaping scientists’ professional experiences and identities. Scientists form groups which are at a lower level of analysis than the field as a whole, but which play a part in what they will consider to be important, and what they will be likely to overlook. Furthermore, Bourdieu’s field theory has been attacked on the grounds that the habitus only accounts for reproduction of the field and cannot account for change (e.g., Gartman, 1991, Alexander, 1995, Griswold. 1998). Critics argue that” the interlocking concepts of field, capital, and habitus depict an airtight system in which structures produce individuals who in turn reproduce structures” (Sallaz and Zavisca, 2007: 25). Bourdieu has responded by citing changes in particular fields, such as revolutionary Algeria, where the everyday world can no longer be taken for granted. Situations such as these create25“space for symbolic strategies aimed at exploiting the discrepancies between the nominal and the real” (Bourdieu, 1984: 481). But events such as the drastic reorganization of society are rare, and do not account for changes in fields outside of such contexts. In cases such as political revolutions, Bourdieu’s field theory does not so much explain changes in the field as is does excuse itself from extraneous circumstances.The remainder of this paper will be given over to addressing these shortcomings in Bourdieu’s field theory of science. Although it is seldom acknowledged, Karl Mannheim and Pierre Bourdieu share fundamental views on the relation between social position and knowledge, and I will argue that Bourdieu’s field theory can be enriched when a Mannheimian analysis of group positions is taken.MANNHEIM, IDEOLOGY, AND UTOPIAWith the publication of the original German edition of Ideology and Utopia in 1929, Karl Mannheim grew to be an influential social theorist within the German speaking world. Mannheim’s contribution was to redefine how thinking and knowledge were to be considered in reference to social structure. Mannheim’s sociology of knowledge argues that styles of thought are a consequence of lived conditions, that lived conditions are organized according to sociological categories, and that each sociological category’s style of thought is shaped by interactions with others (1936). Knowledge, he argues, “is from the very beginning a co-operative process of group life, in which everyone unfolds his knowledge within the framework of a common fate, a common activity, and the overcoming of common difficulties (in which, however, each has a different share)” (1936: 29). The Mannheimian sociology of knowledge specifies that the “individual is born into a world where political and social ideas are already preformed into patterns and have a structure which is independent of the individual” (Turner, 1995: 721), and thus the individual takes on the characteristics of thought which are a consequence of the group outlook within which he is situated. From this perspective, the unique experiences of particular groups give rise to corresponding modes of thinking.These modes of thought simultaneously exist among other modes of thought stemming from other social groups. One characteristic feature of Mannheim’s sociology of knowledge is its reliance on structural analysis: the style of thought corresponding to a particular group cannot be understood without reference to the ideas of other social groups with which it interacts. Groups “do not confront the objects of the world . . . as solitary beings. On the contrary they act with and against one other in diversely organized groups, and while doing so they think with and against one another” (Mannheim, 1936: 4). This structural relationship between modes of thought stemming from the concrete experiences of different social groups results in competition over what Mannheim calls “the correct social diagnosis” (1952: 196); different groups compete for control over what counts as the proper perspective on the social condition.These modes of thought, however, do not arise arbitrarily from social conditions but tend to reflect the various interests of the groups from which they spring. The ideas flowing from a particular group tend to justify the interests of that group, and so contain an element of incongruence with the structure of the intellectual field as a whole. In this sense, ideas become ideologies which imperfectly reflect reality. Mannheim builds on Marx’s critique of bourgeois ideology, in which Marx had identified political liberalism as a justification for capitalist relations of production. He acknowledges the significance of Marx’s insight, crediting him as the first to give systematic attention to how ideas are a reflection of lived conditions (Mannheim, 1936: 72-5). However, Mannheim faults Marx for claiming to attack liberalism from a politically neutral position. Marxism, Mannheim argues, is no less an ideology than liberalism, even if it represents the conditions of a different class of people. To Mannheim, ideologies cannot be avoided because they are the intellectual dimension of lived experience.Mannheim’s theory of ideology considers several levels of ideological consciousness. An awareness of a particular ideology corresponds to the realization that an individual opponent is making use of biased ideas to justify interests. Total ideology shifts the focus to the collective, exposing the biases of thought in the ideas of whole social groups. Those who make use of the special form of the total conception of ideology only expose as ideological those ideas which correspond to groups other than26one’s own; Mannheim locates orthodox Marxism here. Finally, the g eneral form of the total conception of ideology subjects all points of view, including the analyst’s, to sociological analysis (see Mannheim, 1936:Ch.2). According to Mannheim, the general form of the total conception of ideology is the proper domain of the sociology of knowledge because it treats all ideas as emerging from concrete existence, and so it gives special privilege to none. From the Mannheimian perspective, ideology loses its negative connotation and becomes a constitutive element of social life, a necessary consequence of existence. Because each particular group is situated in a unique position relative to the entire intellectual landscape it can only formulate ideas consistent with that position, and so ideology is merely a way of making sense of the world within the limits imposed by social structure. This is what Rayner has referred to as the “neutral” conception of ideology which “dispenses with the idea that ideology is parasitic upon existing disciplines such as history or science and can be understood negatively as a simple falling-away from well-understood standards of truth or rationality” (1989: 375). Ideology, then, is incongruence, but one which cannot be separated from concrete existence.In defining ideology as incongruence between ideas and reality, Mannheim includes utopianism as a special kind of ideology that is directed at social change. Ricoeur has recognized the significance of this synthesis, noting that Mannheim “was perhaps the initial person to link ideology and utopia together under the general problematic of noncongruence [sic]” (1986:159). The difference between ideology and utopia, however, may be found in their differing political aims: ideologies justify and perpetuate extant social arrangements, while utopias “tend to shatter, either partially or wholly, the order of things prevailing at the time” (Mannheim, 1936: 192). Both ideologies and utopias are incomplete interpretations groups make of a larger intellectual landscape of which they have only a partial view. The difference is thatideologies function to maintain social stability while utopias press for social change. Mannheim executes a slight redefinition of the term which was coined by Thomas More in 1516. To Mannheim, utopian thought is not confined to stories of places that are “no place” but encompasses all forms of thought which intend to alter social relationships as they stand.3 He “goes out of his way to reject the popular meaning of utopia as wish fulfillment, or a hope or dream that is in principle unrealizable” (Kumar,2006: 173). Instead of utopias being defined as unrealizable, Mannheim insists that they are the vehicles of social change, the modes of thought which work to discredit the ideologies which legitimate the status quo. Utopias are “those ideas and values in which are contained in condensed form the unrealized and the unfulfilled tendencies which represent the needs of each age. These intellectual elements then become the explosive material for bursting the limits of the existing order” (Mannheim, 1936: 199). Because utopian thought is defined by Mannheim as a program for altering existing conditions, utopianism is inseparable from purposeful change; it is the very embodiment of it. As such, it is a primary component of a dynamic society. Ricoeur summarizes Mannheim’s position: If we could imagine a society where everything is realized, there congruence would exist. Thesociety, however, would also be dead, because there would be no distance, no ideals, noproject at all. Mannheim fights against those who claim – and herald – that we are now livingin the time of the death of ideology and utopia. The suppression of noncongruence, thesuppression of the disconnection between ideals and reality, would be the death of society(1986: 180).However, as a form of incongruence, utopias suffer the same shortcomings as ideologies. Because, like all ideologies, they are espoused by social groups who may only think within the bounds which their social structural position permits them to, utopias fail to grasp the total social landscape, and are always responses to perspectives which only partially grasp reality. Mannheim argues that utopian groups “are intellectually so strongly interested in the destruction and transformation of a given society that they unwittingly see only those elements in the situation which tend to negate it. Their thinking is incapable of correctly diagnosing an existing condition of society” (1936: 40). And so utopian modes of thought tend to treat as factual only those elements of reality that are congruous with its own perspective. This is what Roy Jacques has called “crypto-utopia,” or a brand of utopianism which fails to acknowledge the situatedness of its claims; it is “a form of idealized vision of the world that pretends not to be a vision at 3 Thomas More’s original coinage of the term “utopia” was a play on the Greek words “outopia” and “eutopia”, the former meaning “the place that is nowhere” and the latter meaning “the good place”.27。